ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW - Sarah aggaou


ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW

مجلة قانونك
ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW


ARTICLE
A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW

Realized by: Sarah  aggaou
Researcher at the Faculty of Law, Agdal, Rabat



INTRODUCTION
criminal procedure, extensive case law, and statestatutes. It comes into use when a litigant appeals the decision of a judge or jury, arguing that an error of law was made attrial that resulted in an incorrect decision or verdict. The appellate court then must decide whether the error was seriousenough to strike down the decision made at trial.review for harmless error involves a complicated test that applies to stateand federal laws as well as rules of procedure. If an error is held to be serious, the appellate court is likely to set aside the decision of the trial court and may order a new trial. If it deems the error harmless, the appellate court affirms the lowercourt’s decision. The doctrine of harmless error thus prevents an unnecessary new trial when the error alleget would not have affected the outcome at trail[1].
Harmless error jurisprudence grew out of a late-nineteenth-century development in english law. Before 1873, englishcourts automatically reversed decisions in cases where an error was committed at trial. In 1873, parliament put an end to thispractice in civil cases by permitting reversals only in cases of susbstantial error. As the author raymond A. kimble has noted, u.s .law slowly adopted the idea in order to limit the number of retrials in u.s.courts[2].
             In 1919, congress first applied the harmless error doctrine to appellate courts, ordering them «  to give judgment afteran examination of the record without regard to errors or defects which do not affect the substantial rights of the partie ». by the midtwentieth century, harmless error jurispudence was growing. The court in chapman ruled that defendants were not necessarily entitled to a new trial simly because constitutional violations had occurred at triam. Itdirected appellate courts to dismiss arguments about certain constitutional errors when these:
 «  are so unimportant andinsignificant that they may, comsistent with the federal constitution, be deemed harmless, not requiring automatic reversal of a conviction »[3].
    The Court has been faithful to the belief that the harmless-error doctrine is essential to preserve the “principle that the central purpose of a criminal trial is to decide the factual question of the defendant’s guilt or innocence, and promotes public respect for the criminal process by focusing on the underlying fairness of the trial rather than on the virtually inevitable presence of immaterial error.”[4]
[T]he Court in pursuing the theme of guilt/innocence must beware lest a dominant value become an exclusive one; lest a functional inquiry into a right’s consequences for accuracy crystallize a functionalist reduction of the right’s content[5].
A court using the method I propose would begin by identifying the interest (or range of interests) protected by whichever procedural rule was infringed. The interests that underpin various rules in criminal procedure are not all cut from the same cloth, as noted above, and the interests that are relevant to harmless error review in each case would reflect this variability. This is the first sense in which the style of harmless error analysis I envision is contextual[6].
After discerning the pertinent universe of legally protected interests, a court would conduct contextual harmless error review, in accord with the principle that remedies should generally correspond to “the nature of the interests that comprise the rights” they are meant to enforce[7]. The court would balance the redressable harm caused by the error against the social cost of reversal and reverse if the former outweighs the latter. The harm engendered by error of course varies from one case to the next, as does the cost of reversal, which depends substantially on the type of reversal (in the broad and nontechnical sense in which I am using that term) sought by the defendant[8].
Shifting from the current result-based harmless error regime to the one I propose would have far-reaching benefits. Perhaps the most important effects of the reform I advocate relate to the large group of cases in which reviewing courts find that the prosecution presented overwhelming evidence against the defendant apart from and untainted by the error. Result-based harmless error rules almost universally forbid reversal in these situations, no matter how egregious the error, on the theory that the factfinder most likely would have rendered the same decision based on the untainted evidence had the error not occurred[9].
 By disassociating the defendant’s entitlement to reversal from the gravity of the error in cases where the untainted evidence is overwhelming, result-based harmless error review gives prosecutors and trial judges unbridled license in those cases to commit error of the very worst kinds without risking reversal[10].
My proposal would alleviate this problem by leaving reversal on the table regardless of how strong the prosecution’s untainted evidence might be. This is not to say that the strength of the prosecution’s case would be irrelevant. Insofar as the errors under review implicate only truth-furthering interests — or non-truth-furthering interests that are result-correlated in the sense described below[11] — contextual harmless error analysis would yield outcomes similar or even identical to those produced by the current result-based rules. And even for errors that impinge on non-truth-furthering interests that are result-independent (again, as defined below[12]), the reliability of the untainted evidence retains some relevance to contextual harmless error review because it is generally more costly to reverse an outcome backed by compelling evidence than an outcome that has weaker evidentiary support.
But a contextual approach to harmless error review would not automatically treat the existence of overwhelming untainted evidence as dispositive with respect to rules that protect result-independent interests. No matter how compelling the evidence against the defendant, a court applying contextual harmless error review would still need to consider whether the error harmed result-independent interests to a degree warranting reversal[13].
Despite all this, I acknowledge that there are plausible arguments in favor of retaining the result-based harmless error regime. One might defend it, for example, on the grounds that (1) injuries to resultindependent interests, though regrettable, are rarely if ever important enough to justify reversal,[14] (2) result-based harmless error review achieves a satisfactory level of systemic compliance with the law by disincentivizing errors caused by a desire to tilt the result in the prosecution’s favor,[15] and (3) civil, disciplinary, and other remedies are superior, compared with reversal, as mechanisms for addressing errors that cause harm to interests unrelated to the outcome.[16]
Although these arguments are not without problems, they would hold together well enough if there were no other viable way of approaching harmless error analysis — if, in other words, automatic reversal were the only alternative to result-based harmless error review. And that is certainly the impression one gets from much of the existing literature about harmless error review. In their zeal to expand the list of procedural errors that are completely exempt from harmless error review of any kind, commentators have for the most part overlooked the possibility of developing alternative methods of harmless error review that are not result-based. As we shall see, courts grade slightly better on this measure:
in one understudied area of criminal procedure that deals with certain types of recusal errors, courts have formulated a non-result-based “special harmless error test” that I regard as a prototype for the method I propose in this Article.[17] But courts have not adapted that test for use outside the narrow doctrinal context in which it emerged. And the academic literature relating to harmless error review has inexplicably failed even to notice its existence[18].
This Article raises as many questions as it answers. My purpose is not to identify and weigh all of the potential costs and benefits of transitioning from the current remedial order to one organized around contextual harmless error analysis. Rather, I intend to show that contextual harmless error review is a normatively plausible alternative to the current result-based rules, and to lay the groundwork for future scholarship that can systematically assess its viability[19].
I.          THE NARROW PATHS TO REVERSAL FOR CRIMINAL PROCEDURE ERRORS
In this Part, I advance three primary claims. First, harmless error review as currently applied in criminal cases almost invariably focuses on whether the error might have affected the outcome of the proceeding under review[20]. My label for this mode of inquiry is result-based harmless error review[21].
Second, harmless error review has largely crowded out alternative pathways to reversal such as automatic reversal and reversals based on a court’s supervisory power, albeit without completely eliminating them. And finally, the main ideas that commentators have put forward in their longstanding efforts to improve the law of harmless error have not borne much fruit. Those who argue that harmless error analysis should pay little or no heed to the prosecution’s untainted evidence and should instead simply ask whether the error affected the outcome propose an impossible task, as courts cannot avoid examining the error’s context to discern its probable effect, and that context necessarily includes the untainted evidence. Others urge courts to exempt large swaths of criminal procedure from existing harmless error rules, but without offering any viable replacement to sweeten the deal. Courts have balked at this proposal. If we are to address the serious concern that “nearly ubiquitous use of a harmless error rule focusing on the outcome of the trial . . . denigrates important constitutional protections . . . that promote values other than the reliability of [guilty] verdicts,” we will need to look for solutions elsewhere[22].
A.     Result-Based Harmless Error Review
    This section explores how the prevailing result-based method of harmless error review works, the principles it embodies, and from whence it came. I argue that much of the existing case law and commentary misunderstands important facets of the modern harmless error doctrine’s conceptual structure. These misunderstandings have impeded efforts to diagnose the ailment that has afflicted our courts of review and to determine how best to cure it. Clearing up these matters at the outset will facilitate the normative analysis that follows later in the Article[23].
Federal courts typically apply one of three rules when conducting harmless error review in criminal cases. These rules fairly represent the broader universe of harmless error rules currently used by American courts, subject to a few exceptions[24]. For most constitutional claims preserved by a timely defense objection (and reviewed on direct appeal), Chapman v. California[25]  holds that courts may declare the error harmless only if the prosecution “prove[s] beyond a reasonable doubt that the error . . . did not contribute to the verdict.[26]”  Federal courts reviewing preserved nonconstitutional claims, by contrast, ordinarily apply the standard set forth in Kotteakos v. United States[27], which asks whether the court can say with “fair assurance” that the outcome “was not substantially swayed by the error.[28]” (Federal courts also apply Kotteakos with respect to constitutional errors when considering those errors on collateral review, as in Brecht v. Abrahamson[29], rather than on direct appeal.[30] ) And the federal harmless error standard for


[4] Arizona v. Fulminante, 499 U.S. 279, 308 (1991) (quoting Delaware v. Van Arsdall, 475 U.S.
673, 681 (1986) (citation omitted))
 Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.from P 1791 to 1826
[5] Robert M. Cover & T. Alexander Aleinikoff, Dialectical Federalism: Habeas Corpus and the
Court, 86 YALE L.J. 1035, 1092 (1977).
 Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[6]  Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.from P 1791 to 1826
[7] JAMES M. FISCHER, UNDERSTANDING REMEDIES § 3.1, at 11 (3d ed. 2014) (“The nature
of an available remedy is clearly tied to the substantive right at issue.”).
[8]  Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.from P 1791 to 1826
[9] As explained below, there are rare situations in which a court applying result-based harmless error rules must reverse, despite the court’s opinion that the prosecution’s untainted evidence is overwhelming, infra note 69. This situation occurs when the record indicates that the factfinder did not find the evidence to be overwhelming. A jury might, for example, evince doubt regarding aspects of the prosecution’s case by sending notes during deliberations, delivering a split verdict that convicts the defendant on some counts while acquitting or failing to achieve unanimity on others, or by deliberating for a period long enough to suggest that the jury did notview the case as a slam dunk for the prosecution.
[10]  Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.from P 1791 to 1826
[11] See infra p. 1814.  Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[12] See infra p. 1814. Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[13] Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW. P 1791 to 1826
[14] See, e.g., United States v. Mechanik, 475 U.S. 66, 72 (1986). But see, e.g., Stacy & Dayton, supra note 13, at 85.. Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[15] See, e.g., William R. Newlin, Recent Decision, Fahy v. Connecticut, 375 U.S. 85 (1963), 25 U. PITT. L. REV. 601, 60304 (1964). But cf. sources cited supra note 13. Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[16] See, e.g., Landes & Posner, supra note 10, at 186. But there is broad agreement that these remedies, however desirable they might be in the abstract, are currently all but nonexistent and thus that “for criminal defendants whose rights are violated at trial, it is ‘reversal or nothing.’” Meltzer, supra note 7, at 31 (modifying Justice Harlan’s statement in Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents of Federal Bureau of Narcotics, 403 U.S. 388 (1971), that “[f]or [innocent] people in Bivens’ shoes, it is damages or nothing,” id. at 410 (Harlan, J., concurring in the judgment)). And although I agree that criminal defendants also need more expansive access to remedies other than reversal, proposals of that kind and efforts like mine to improve the rules that determine when criminal procedure remedies (in particular, reversal) are warranted are not mutually exclusive. See Nancy Leong & Aaron Belzer, Enforcing Rights, 62 UCLA L. REV. 306, 346 (2015) (discussing the advantages of “multiple remedial avenues” for procedural error). . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[17] E.g., Scott v. United States, 559 A.2d 745, 74647 (D.C. 1989) (en banc) (adopting Liljeberg v. Health Servs. Acquisition Corp., 486 U.S. 847 (1988)); see infra section II.C, pp. 182023. . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[18] To be sure, commentators have helpfully analyzed the Liljeberg harmless error method as it relates to recusal law. See, e.g., Leslie W. Abramson, Appearance of Impropriety: Deciding When a Judge’s Impartiality “Might Reasonably Be Questioned,14 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 55, 7375 (2000). My point is simply that the potential significance of Liljeberg and its progeny to the broader debate about harmless error review has thus far gone unexamined.  . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[19] . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[20] See infra notes 4051 and accompanying text.
. Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[21] . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[22] . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[23] . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[24] I discuss the most important of these exceptions — the harmless error rule applicable to certain types of recusal errors set forth in Liljeberg v. Health Services Acquisition Corp., 486 U.S. 847, 86265 (1988) — in section II.C, infra pp. 182023. . Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.fraom P 1791 to 1826
[25] 386 U.S. 18 (1967).
[26] Id. at 24. Chapman left open the possibility that there might be “some constitutional rights so basic to a fair trial that their infraction can never be treated as harmless error,” id. at 23, citing as examples the rule against admission of “coerced confession[s],” the “right to counsel,” and the requirement of an “impartial judge,” id. at 23 n.8. To mention just a few of the many excellent works analyzing Chapman and its progeny, see, for example, ROGER J. TRAYNOR, THE RIDDLE OF HARMLESS ERROR (1970); John M. Greabe, The Riddle of Harmless Error Revisited, 54 HOUS. L. REV. 59 (2016); Philip J. Mause, Harmless Constitutional Error: The Implications of Chapman v. California, 53 MINN. L. REV. 519 (1969); Meltzer, supra note 7; and Stephen A.
Saltzburg, The Harm of Harmless Error, 59 VA. L. REV. 988 (1973).
Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.from P 1791 to 1826
[27] 328 U.S. 750 (1946).
Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.from P 1791 to 1826
[28] Id. at 765.
[29]507 U.S. 619 (1993).
Justin Murray, ARTICLE A CONTEXTUAL APPROACH TO HARMLESS ERROR REVIEW.from P 1791 to 1826
[30] Id. at 63738. The Court has since reaffirmed Brecht in Fry v. Pliler, 551 U.S. 112 (2007). In that case, the Court rejected the defendant’s claim that Congress implicitly superseded Brecht by enacting 28 U.S.C. § 2254(d)(1) (2012), which requires federal courts to restrict their collateral review of state court proceedings to rulings that are “contrary to, or involve[ ] . . . unreasonable application[s] of, clearly established Federal law.” Fry, 551 U.S. at 119 (quoting § 2254(d)(1)); id.
at 11920.


للتتمة المقال يرجى تحميله أسفله 

من أجل تحميل هذا المقال كاملا -  إضغط هناك - أو أسفله

قانونك

من أجل تحميل العدد الرابع  - إضغط هنا أو أسفله على الصورة

مجلة قانونك - العدد الثالث